The set of terms of first-order logic (also known as first-order predicate calculus) is defined by the following rules:
1. A variable is a term.
2. If
is an
-place
function symbol (with
)
and
,
...,
are terms, then
is a term.
If
is an
-place
predicate symbol (again with
) and
, ...,
are terms, then
is an atomic
statement.
Consider the sentential formulas and
, where
is a sentential formula,
is the universal quantifier ("for
all"), and
is the existential quantifier ("there
exists").
is called the scope of the respective quantifier,
and any occurrence of variable
in the scope of a quantifier
is bound by the closest
or
. The variable
is free in the formula
if at least one of its occurrences in
is not bound by any quantifier within
.
The set of sentential formulas of first-order predicate calculus is defined by the following rules:
1. Any atomic statement is a sentential formula.
2. If
and
are sentential formulas, then
(NOT
),
(
AND
),
(
OR
), and
(
implies
) are sentential formulas
(cf. propositional calculus).
3. If
is a sentential formula in which
is a free variable, then
and
are sentential formulas.
In formulas of first-order predicate calculus, all variables are object variables serving as arguments of functions and predicates. (In second-order predicate calculus, variables may denote predicates, and quantifiers may apply to variables standing for predicates.) The set of axiom schemata of first-order predicate calculus is comprised of the axiom schemata of propositional calculus together with the two following axiom schemata:
(1)
| |
(2)
|
where
is any sentential formula in which
occurs free,
is a term,
is the result of substituting
for the free occurrences of
in sentential formula
, and all occurrences of all variables
in
are free in
.
Rules of inference in first-order predicate calculus are the Modus Ponens and the two following rules:
(3)
| |
(4)
|
where
is any sentential formula in which
occurs as a free variable,
does not occur as a free variable in formula
, and the notation means that if the
formula above the line is a theorem formally deducted from axioms by application
of inference rules, then the sentential formula
below the line is also a formal theorem.
Similarly to propositional calculus, rules for introduction and elimination of and
can be derived in first-order predicate calculus. For
example, the following rule holds provided that
is the result of substituting variable
for the free occurrences
of
in sentential formula
and all occurrences of
resulting from this substitution are free
in
,
(5)
|
Gödel's completeness theorem established equivalence between valid formulas of first-order predicate calculus and formal theorems of first-order predicate calculus. In contrast to propositional calculus, use of truth tables does not work for finding valid sentential formulas in first-order predicate calculus because its truth tables are infinite. However, Gödel's completeness theorem opens a way to determine validity, namely by proof.